Sunday, August 1, 2010

PRIVITY OF CONTRACT

INTRODUCTION :


The doctrine of privity in contract law provides that a contract cannot confer rights or impose obligations arising under it on any person or agent except the parties to it.

This seems to make adequate sense, in that only parties to contracts should be able to sue to enforce their rights or claim damages as such. However the doctrine has proven problematic due to its implications upon contracts made for the benefit of third parties who are unable to enforce the obligations of the contracting parties.



HISTORY

Prior to 1833 there existed decisions in English allowing provisions of a contract to be enforced by persons not party to it, usually relatives of a promisee. The doctrine of privity emerged alongside the doctrine of consideration, the rules of which state that consideration must move from the promisee. That is to say that if nothing is given for the promise of something to be given in return, that promise is not legally binding unless promised as a deed. 1833 saw the case of Price v. Easton, where a contract was made for work to be done in exchange for payment to a third party. When the third party attempted to sue for the payment, he was held to be not privy to the contract, and as such his claim failed. This was fully linked to the doctrine of consideration, and established as such, with the more famous case of Tweddle v. Atkinson. In this case the plaintiff was unable to sue the executor of his father-in-law, who had promised to the plaintiff's father to make payment to the plaintiff, because he had not provided any consideration to the contract.

The doctrine was developed further in Dunlop Pneumatic Tyre v. Selfridge and Co. Ltd. through the judgement of Lord Haldane.

Privity of Contract played a key role in the development of negligence as well. In the first case of Winterbottom v. Wright (1842), in which Winterbottom, a postal service wagon driver, was injured due to a faulty wheel, attempted to sue the manufacturer Wright for his injuries. The courts however decided that there was no privity of contract between manufacturer and consumer in order to support the Industrial Revolution.

This issue appeared repeatedly until MacPherson v. Buick Motor Co. (1916), a case analogous to Winterbottom v Wright involving a car's defective wheel. Judge Cardozo, writing for the New York Court of Appeals, decided that no privity is required when the manufacturer knows the product is probably dangerous if defective, third parties i.e. consumers will be harmed because of said defect, and there was no further testing after initial sale. Foreseeable injuries occurred from forseeable uses. Cardozo's innovation was to decide that the basis for the claim was that it was a tort not a breach of contract. In this way he finessed the problems caused by the doctrine of privity in a modern industrial society. Although his opinion was only law in New York State, the solution he advanced was widely accepted elsewhere.



Privity of contract

A well-established principle of contract law (see: Contract) is that only the parties to the contract can make claims against it. The archetypal case is Dunlop v Selfrige in which Dunlop took action against Selfridge for breach a contract with an intermediary. The House of Lords ruled that Dunlop were not a party to the contract that was breached, and could therefore not enforce it.

Clearly it is fair that people should not incur obligations in respect of contracts to which they are not party and which offer them no benefits. However the principle of privity does mean that it is difficult to enter a contract that benefits a third party without taking out a separate contract with the third party. For example, in Woodar v Wimpey, Wimpey contracted to pay £850,000 for land to Woodar, and £150,000 to a third party. When Wimpey tried to back out of the deal, they claimed that they could not be sued for the £150,000 because of privity. This claim was upheld by the House of Lords. The case of Tweddle v Atkinson rested on the same issues.

While there have long been specific statutes allowing third-party rights under contracts (motor insurance, for example) there were repeated calls for the law on privity to be reformed to extend the abilities of third parties in general to enforce a contract for their benefits The ContractsRightsOfThirdPartiesAct1999 goes some way towards this.

Briefly, a third party can enforce a contract if:

• the contract specifically provides for this, and

• the contract benefits the third party, and

• the allowed third parties must be identified in the contract, and

• the contracting parties consent to the provision for third-party enforcement.

The doctrine of privity poses particular problems for exclusion clauses in contracts.

ContractLaw.


Third-party rights

Privity of contract occurs only between the parties to the contract, most commonly contract of sale of goods or services. Horizontal privity arises when the benefits from a contract are to be given to a third party. Vertical privity involves a contract between two parties, with an independent contract between one of the parties and another individual or company.

If a third party gets a benefit under a contract, it does not have the right to go against the parties to the contract beyond its entitlement to a benefit. An example of this occurs when a manufacturer sells a product to a distributor and the distributor sells the product to a retailer. The retailer then sells the product to a consumer. There is no privity of contract between the manufacturer and the consumer.

This, however, does not mean that the parties do not have another form of action e.g. Donoghue v. Stevenson -- here a friend of Ms. D bought her a bottle of ginger beer, which was defective. Since the contract was between her friend and the shop owner, there was no privity of contract, but it was established that the manufacturer has a duty of care owed to their consumers and she was awarded damages in tort.

Privity is the legal term for a close, mutual, or successive relationship to the same right of property or the power to enforce a promise or warranty.



Exceptions


Common law exceptions

There are exceptions to the general rule, allowing rights to third parties and some impositions of obligations. These are:

• Collateral Contracts (between the third party and one of the contracting parties)

• Trusts (the beneficiary of a trust may sue the trustee to carry out the contract)

• Land Law (restrictive covenants on land are imposed upon subsequent purchasers if the covenant benefits neighbouring land)

• Agency and the assignment of contractual rights are permitted.

Attempts have been made to evade the doctrine by implying trusts (with varying success), constructing the Law of Property Act 1925 s. 56(1) to read the words "other property" as including contractual rights, and applying the concept of restrictive covenants to property other than real property (without success).

Statutory exceptions

The Contracts (Rights of Third Parties) Act 1999 (UK) now provides some reform for this area of law which has been criticised by judges such as Lord Denning and academics as unfair in places. The act states:

1. - (1) Subject to the provisions of this Act, a person who is not a party to a contract (a "third party") may in his own right enforce a term of the contract if-

(a) the contract expressly provides that he may, or

(b) subject to subsection (2), the term purports to confer a benefit on him.

(2) Subsection (1)(b) does not apply if on a proper construction of the contract it appears that the parties did not intend the term to be enforceable by the third party.

This entails that a person who is named in the contract as a person authorised to enforce the contract or a person receiving a benefit from the contract may enforce the contract unless it appears that the parties intended that he may not.

The Act enables the aim of the parties to be fully adhered too. Taking the situation in Beswick v Beswick whereby the only reason why Mr Beswick and his nephew contracted was for the benefit of Mrs Beswick. Under the Act Mrs Beswick would be able to enforce the performance of the contract in her own right. therefore, the Act realises the intentions of the parties.

The law has been welcomed by many as a relief from the strictness of the doctrine, however it may still prove ineffective in professionally drafted documents, as the provisions of this statute may be expressly excluded by the draftsmen.



Third-party beneficiaries

In Australia, it has been held that third-party beneficiaries may uphold a promise made for its benefit in a contract to which it is not a party (Trident General Insurance Co Ltd v. McNiece Bros Pty Ltd (1988) 165 CLR 107). There were caveats however; the two parties to the contract are able to vary the terms of the contract as they see fit, unless the third-party has relied on the promise, and the promisor is subject to any defences that it would have had, had the promise been enforced by the promisee. It is important to note though that the decision in Trident had no clear ratio.

Although damages are the usual remedy for the breach of a contract for the benefit of a third party, if damages are inadequate, specific performance may be granted (Beswick v. Beswick [1968] AC 59).

The issue of third-party beneficiaries has appeared in cases where a stevedore has claimed it is covered under the exclusion clauses in a bill of lading. In order for this to succeed, four factors must be made out:

• The bill of lading must clearly intend to benefit the third party.

• It is clear that when the carrier contracts with the consignor, it also contracts as an agent of the stevedore.

• The carrier must have had authority by the stevedores to act on its behalf, or the stevedores must later endorse the actions of the carrier.

• Any difficulties with consideration moving from the stevedores must be made out.

The last issue was explored in New Zealand Shipping Co Ltd v. A M Satterthwaite & Co Ltd [1975] AC 154, where it was held that the stevedores had provided consideration for the benefit of the exclusion clause by the discharge of goods from the ship.

New Zealand has enacted the Contracts Privity Act 1982, which enables third parties to sue if they sufficiently identified as beneficiaries by the contract, and there is it is expressed or implied they should be able to enforce this benefit.

THEORIES ON CORPORATE PERSONALITY: REAL OR FICTITIOUS?

INTRODUCTION
The decision of House of Lords in Salomon v A Salomon & Co. Ltd had a lasting influence in corporation law. It is often credited with the principle of separate legal entity of the corporation distinct from the members.


Though there is no doubt that the Salomon case had play a significant role in company law, the decision in this case was hardly the origin of the separate legal entity principle. The legal entity of beings other than the human has long been recognized prior to 1897, in which the Salomon case was decided. The jurisprudence theories on juristic person had been established since the early Roman law to justify the existence of legal person other than the human. The State, religious bodies and education institutions had long been recognized as having legal entity distinct from the members.

The acceptance of the corporate personality of a company basically means that another non-human entity is recognized to assume a legal entity. This can be seen from the many theories of jurisprudence on corporate personality. Majority of the principal jurisprudence theories on corporate personality contended that the legal entity of the corporation is artificial. The fiction, concession, symbolist and purpose theories supported the contention that existence of corporation as a legal person is not real. It only exists because the law of the state recognized it as legal person and it is recognized either for certain purpose or objectives. The fiction theory, for example, clearly stated that the existence of corporation as a legal person is purely fiction and that the rights attached to it totally depend on how much the law imputes upon it by fiction.

THE COMMON LAW PERSPECTIVES
Generally, there are two types of person which the law recognized, namely the natural and artificial person. The former is confined merely for human beings while the latter is generally referred to any being other than human being which the law recognized as having duties and rights . One of the most recognized artificial persons is the corporation.

Legal scholars, particularly the jurists, have always explored the issue on the recognition of corporation as a legal person. In the study of jurisprudence, the separate legal personality of corporation is based upon theories, which are concentrated upon the philosophical explanation of the existence of personality in beings other than human individuals. W. Friedman stated that:

“All law exists for the sake of liberty inherent in each individual; therefore the original concept of personality must coincide with the idea of man.”

Even though there are many theories which attempted to explain the nature of corporate personality, none of them is said to be dominant. It is claimed that while each theory contains elements of truth, none can by itself sufficiently interpret the phenomenon of juristic person. Nonetheless, there are five principal theories, which are used to explain corporate personality, namely, the fiction theory, realist theory, the purpose theory, the bracket theory and the concession theory.


THE FICTION THEORY

The fiction theory of corporation is said to be promulgated by Pope Innocent IV (1243-1254). This theory is supported by many famous jurists, particularly, Savigny and Salmond. According to this theory, the legal personality of entities other than human beings is the result of a fiction. Hence, not being a human being, corporation cannot be a real person and cannot have any personality on its own. Originally, the outward form that corporate bodies are fictitious personality was directed at ecclesiastic bodies. The doctrine was used to explain that the ecclesiastic colleges or universities could not be excommunicated or be guilty of a delict as they have neither a body nor a will. The famous case of Salomon v A Salomon Co Ltd is a proof of the English court adoption of the fiction theory. In this case, Lord Halsbury stated that the important question to decide was whether in truth an artificial creation of the legislature had been validly constituted. It was held that as the company had fulfilled requirements of the Companies Act, the company becomes a person at law, independent and distinct from its members.

Salmond, made it clear that a human being is the only natural person while legal persons govern any subject matter other than a human being to which the law attributes personality. States, corporations and institutions cannot have rights of a person but they are treated as if they are persons. Under this theory, rights and duties attached to corporation as artificial person totally depend on how much the law imputes to it by fiction.

The personality the corporation enjoys is not inherent in it but as conceded by the state. Due to the close connection made in this theory as regards to relation of legal personality and the power of the state, fiction theory was claimed to be similar to the theory of sovereignty of state which is also known as the concession theory.

THE CONCESSION THEORY

The concession theory is basically linked with the philosophy of the sovereign national state. It is said to be essentially a product of the rise of the national state at a time when there were rivals between religious congregations and organizations of feudal origin for the claim of national state to complete sovereignty. Under the concession theory, the state is considered to be in the same level as the human being and as such, it can confer on or withdraw legal personality from other groups and associations within its jurisdictions as an attribute of its sovereignty. Hence, a juristic person is merely a concession or creation of the state.

Concession theory is often regarded as the offspring of the fiction theory as it has similar claim that the corporations within the state have no legal personality except as it is conceded by the state. Exponents of the fiction theory, for example, Savigny, Dicey and Salmond are found to support this theory. Nonetheless, it is that while the fiction theory is ultimately a philosophical theory that a corporation is merely a name and a thing of the intellect, the concession theory is indifferent as regards to the question of the reality of a corporation in that it focuses on the sources of which the legal power is derived. Dicey took the view that sovereignty is merely a legal conception which indicates the law-making power unrestricted by any legal limits.



THE PURPOSE THEORY

This theory is also known as the theory of Zweckvermogen. Similar to the fiction and concession theories, it declares that only human beings can be a person and have rights. Entities other human is regarded as an artificial person and merely function as a legal device for protecting or giving effect to some real purpose. As corporations are not human, they can merely be regarded as juristic or artificial person. Under this theory, juristic person is no person at all but merely as a “subject less” property destined for a particular purpose and that there is ownership but no owner. The juristic person is not constructed round a group of person but based on the object and purpose. The property of the juristic person does not belong to anybody but it may be dedicated and legally bound by certain objects. This theory rationalized the existence of many charitable corporations or organizations, such as trade unions, which have been recognized as legal persons for certain purposes and have continuing fund. It is also closely linked with the legal system which regard the institution of public law (Anstalt) and the endowment of private law (Stiftung) as legal personalities.



THE SYMBOLIST THEORY

This theory is also known as the “bracket” theory. It was set up by Ihering and later developed particularly by Marquis de Vareilles-SommiĆ©res. Basically, this theory is similar to the fiction theory in that it recognizes that only human beings have interests and rights of a legal person. According to Ihering, the conception of corporate personality is essential and merely an economic device by which simplify the task of coordinating legal relations. Hence, when it is necessary, it is emphasized that the law should look behind the entity to discover the real state of affairs. This is clearly in line with the principle of lifting of the corporate veil. Under this theory, rights are not inherent attributes of the human will and that an individual is not a subject of right by reason that he possesses a will. On the contrary, the will is at the service of law and it is the interest of man which the law protects.

The symbolist theory is often acknowledged for its availability to justify corporate personality from non-legal facts but it has been repeatedly rejected by the courts in common law jurisdictions because it denies the law by deducing that the only legal relation which is fixed and certain can be discovered by removing the ‘brackets’ of the corporation and analyzing the relations of the human beings involved.



THE REALIST THEORY

The founder of this theory was a German jurist, Johannes Althusius while its most prominent advocate is Otto von Gierke, who not only responsible for the scholarly wisdom of his writings but also as the challenger to the entire basis of Roman jurisprudence. According to this theory, a legal person is a real personality in an extra juridical and pre-juridical sense of the word. It also assumes that the subjects of rights need not belong merely to human beings but to every being which possesses a will and life of its own. As such, being a juristic person and as ‘alive’ as the human being, a corporation is also subjected to rights. Under the realist theory, a corporation exists as an objectively real entity and the law merely recognizes and gives effect to its existence. The realist jurist also contended that the law has no power to create an entity but merely having the right to recognize or not to recognize an entity.

A corporation from the realist perspective is a social organism while a human is regarded as a physical organism. The realists contended that action of the corporation is deem to be carried out on its own, similar to the way of the normal person and not by its agents or representatives like those of the incapable, such as the infant and insane. While human uses his bodily organ to do an act, the corporation uses men for that purpose. Some of the realist theory followers even claimed that similar to the human being, juristic person also has organs.

This theory is found to be favored more by sociologists rather than by lawyers. While discussing the realism of the corporate personality, most of the realist jurist claimed that the fiction theory failed to identify the relation of law with the society in general. The main defect of the fiction theory according to the realist jurist is the ignorance of sociological facts that evolved around law making process. Hence, by ignoring the ‘real capacity and functions’ of corporation in the real world, the fiction jurists had failed to see the ‘live’ possessed by a corporation. The realist contended that by rejecting the fiction theory, one would succeed to reject an abstract conception and untrue account of the reality with which the practical lawyer has to deal.

According to the realist jurist, lawyers have to acquire the habit to depart from the plain meaning of law and go behind the scenes of the legal platform for the realization and justice which law is supposed to introduce to life.
CONCLUSION

From the discussion on jurisprudence theories of corporate personality, it is observed that main arguments lie between the fiction and realist theories. The fiction theory claimed that the entity of corporation as a legal person is merely fictitious and only exist with the intendment of the law. On the other hand, from the realist point of view, the entity of the corporation as a legal person is not artificial or fictitious but real and natural. The realist also contended that the law merely has the power to recognize a legal entity or refuse to recognize it but the law has no power to create an entity.

Referring to the English company law case law, it can be seen that in most cases, the court adopted the fiction theory. Salomon v A Salomon Co Ltd is the most obvious example. It is also observed that fiction theory provide the most acceptable reasoning in justifying the circumstances whereby court lifted the corporate veil of corporation. If the entity of the corporation is real, then the court would not have the right to decide the

Circumstances where there is separate legal entity of the corporation should be set aside. No human being has the right to decide circumstances whereby the entity of another human being should be set aside. Only law has such privilege.

Nonetheless, the realist contention that the corporation obtain its entity as a legal person not because the law granted it to them but because it is generated through its day to day transaction which are later accepted and recognized by law also seem acceptable.

LIMITED LIABLITY PARTNERSHIP – A BUSINESS STRUCTURE WITH LIMITED LIABILITY AND UNLIMITED OPPORTUNITIES.

LLP being a hybrid between the two traditional forms, the paper explains how the LLP is a separate legal entity, being liable to the full extent of its assets, but at the same time, the liability of the partners is restricted to their agreed contribution. It is widely accepted as being an advantageous business model because it is organized and operates on the basis of an agreement. Also, it provides the flexibility without imposing detailed legal and procedural requirements, enabling professional expertise and initiative to combine with financial risk taking capacity in an innovative and efficient manner.


The paper brings out this concept, supplementing the information available with recommendations from various committees appointed by the government like the Naresh Chandra Committee and the Dr. J.J. Irani Committee. Most importantly, what has to be realized is that this concept of LLP has been found to be necessary as a separate concept because if a utopian situation is taken that the liability of a joint stock company is made unlimited, it may be beneficial to the economy, but is not as useful for the members of the company, including other stock holders. Therefore, instead of trying to convert one traditional form to a new form, the whole concept of Limited Liability Partnership is being introduced which brings about the specificity that is required on a scale such as this.

The paper also brings a comparative analysis between company, limited liability partnership and partnership firm which tells us how it is beneficial from the same, and how can a person’s with sharp mind but less money can have an extra edge over the others. It also provides suggestions regarding different issues of tax, bringing transparency and clarity of work, and how government can be a good facilitator and to work accordingly to make the Indian economy more efficient in the global market.